Journal

Branching out: Could we give legal rights to trees?

By on
12

The notion that a natural object could be a rights holder is not as bizarre as it first seems, writes Oxford Brookes law grad Paul Wyard

In the last few years environmental issues such as deforestation, the climate crisis, and plastic pollution have enjoyed more attention in the news than they previously did.

In times gone by, membership of Greenpeace would have caused some to form stereotypical, new-age assumptions about you, whereas today joining Extinction Rebellion gives rise to no such stigma. Whether you’re a tree-hugging, sandal-wearing, all organic vegan or simply thinking about switching to a bamboo toothbrush, we’re all increasingly aware of the pejorative impact that humans are having on our planet. Not least politicians, who continuously fail to reach consensus on how the international community should manage various environmental problems.

However, in amongst the environmental hullabaloo, in an odd Guardian article here, or a chance TED Talk there, there are some who think that there should be a paradigm shift in the way we think about the degradation of nature — they think that trees (and other natural objects) should have their own legal rights.

“Don’t be silly,” I hear you cry. “Trees can’t have rights, they’re not even human!” But hold on. The notion that a natural object could be a rights holder is not as bizarre as it first seems. After all, companies, nation states and even ships have legal personality and they’re obviously not human, so it deserves serious consideration.

The idea that trees can have legal rights (hereafter called “the Trees Thesis”) was originally posited by Christopher Stone in an article published in 1972 entitled ‘Should Trees Have Standing? — Toward Legal Rights for Natural Objects’. It became hugely influential in environmental thought and law, particularly after it formed the basis of a dissenting judgment in the American case of Sierra Club v Morton. Stone said that there are three aspects to holding legal rights:

(1) The holder should be able to instigate legal action on their own behalf

(2) The holder’s injury should be considered when calculating damages, and

(3) Damages should directly benefit the holder

The Trees Thesis ensures that natural objects possess these aspects. Environmental groups could apply to a court to be appointed an object’s ‘guardian’. Guardianship would confer the right to act on the object’s behalf, akin to a deputy acting for someone who lacks mental capacity. Natural objects would have specific rights, e.g. a river could have the right to respect to integrity, which would prohibit water pollution. If these rights were breached, a guardian could investigate the resulting environmental damage and take legal action against the breaching party in the object’s own name. If successful, damages would be awarded to the guardian to hold on trust for the natural object. They would then be obliged to use the damages to benefit or restore the object. Proponents argue that current legal frameworks have failed to prevent environmental degradation and that treating nature like people rather than property is the solution.

Want to write for the Legal Cheek Journal?

Find out more

And it has actually already happened. In 2017, New Zealand granted legal personhood to the Whanganui River and, more recently in 2019, Lake Erie in North America also gained legal personhood. But despite these examples, it is difficult to see how the Trees Thesis would actually work in practice in the United Kingdom. Much can be said about each part of the Thesis; however, I want to focus on how one would actually hold damages for a natural object on trust. Any law graduate knows that, as a general rule, English law only allows trusts for people rather than purposes save for a handful of exceptions — these are trusts for animals, monuments or graves, and private religious masses. Given that a trust for a natural object would constitute a purpose trust, it’s highly unlikely that such a trust would be valid under English law, pouring cold water on the Thesis as a whole.

Although, in reality, there are actually lots of perfectly valid purpose trusts in existence. These are the charitable purpose trusts which must satisfy the requirements outlined in the Charities Act 2011 (“The Act”). Obviously, these requirements would have to be met if a trust for a natural object was established this way. The first requirement is that they must have one of the aims listed in section 3 of the Act. As “the advancement of environmental protection” is one such aim, a natural object trust may be halfway to being created. The trust would then have to confer an ascertainable public benefit, as per section 4 of the Act. Given that benefits are determined on a case by case basis, it is reasonable to assume that a natural object trust would confer a wide ecological benefit to the public at large. So is it really that simple?

The problem lies in the fact that the public benefit is just that, a public benefit — a benefit for the public and the public only. As already stated, the Trees Thesis is premised on the assertion that damages should directly benefit the natural object in question. But if a natural object trust was analysed as a charitable trust, this direct benefit would be subverted by a different, independent benefit for the public instead of the object itself. Turning a natural object trust into a charitable trust would therefore be self-refuting and undermine the whole Thesis. This is to say nothing of other practical hurdles. If a natural object could take legal action against a polluter, could an aggrieved person take similar action if a natural object caused damage to them? For instance, if a river burst its banks and flooded a house. Furthermore, what even is a natural object?

It seems unlikely then that trees or other natural objects could ever be given their own legal rights in the United Kingdom. Instead, continued attempts at international political cooperation will be necessary to take on environmental challenges, perhaps paired with the proclamations of Greta Thunberg.

Paul Wyard is an education law paralegal at Sinclairslaw, Cardiff. He graduated last year with a first-class degree in law from Oxford Brookes University. In addition to education law, Paul maintains an interest in environmental, criminal, and medical law.

Want to write for the Legal Cheek Journal?

Find out more

Please bear in mind that the authors of many Legal Cheek Journal pieces are at the beginning of their career. We'd be grateful if you could keep your comments constructive.

12 Comments

Professor Oak

Betteridge’s law strikes again.

Archibald Pomp O'City

“Guardianship would confer the right to act on the object’s behalf, akin to a deputy acting for someone who lacks mental capacity.”

But you can’t compare a tree to a human being who lacks mental capacity. Such a human being was always able to satisfy the first criterion of being able to instigate legal action on their own behalf but for their lack of capacity. A TREE WAS NEVER ABLE TO INSTIGATE LEGAL ACTION ITS OWN BEHALF. Sheesh, are you folk going to be drafting legislation in the years to come? God help us.

Anon

This may come as a shock to you, but I think it’s possible to be born with a lack of mental capacity. Judging by your post, I think you may be a case in point.

Archibald Pomp O'City

“This may come as a shock to you, but I think it’s possible to be born with a lack of mental capacity.”

It is possible to be born a tree, yes. That was never in doubt. And any given human can be born a vegetable, yes, a creature who never uttered a word of sense and had a nurse mopping up their waste not only in their first hours but beyond adolescence. None of this is in dispute.

But even the congenital human vegetable belongs to a class of entities that can instigate legal action on their own behalf, hence the human rights we confer to them. A TREE DOES NOT, AND NO TREE EVER DID.

It’s like supporting a KitKat’s right to not have its fingers snapped and eaten on the grounds that a human also has four fingers and can instigate legal action if somebody snaps and eats them.

Who the devil are you, anyway? What are your credentials?

Anonymous

“After all, companies, nation states and even ships have legal personality and they’re obviously not human, so it deserves serious consideration.“

It really, really doesn’t.

Maocclesfield

Good article Paul. Any system conferring rights of trees (whatever those may be) on another legal entity could be a disaster. It would be a dream come true for nimbys and property developers – consider it in ransom strip terms.

Property barrister

Interesting article – I didn’t know about the Whanganui river!

Presumably the only way to make natural objects a legal person would be through legislation, in which case undoubtedly a statutory trust would be created to deal with holding money on behalf of the tree.

However I’m not sure how giving legal personhood to common objects like trees would work in the real world.

What happens when a tree with legal personhood starts undermining the foundations in my house? Obviously I can’t now chop it down – can I get an injunction against it requiring it to abate the nuisance? Can I commit it to prison for breach?
If its on my land, and I revoke any licence for occupation, can I charge it use and occupation?
Do I need the consent of its guardians before I prune it?

I would have thought that the ecological aims of the “Tree Thesis” could be entirely met by an extension to Tree Preservation Orders, rather than completely overhauling english private law.

Alan Robertshaw

That was a great article Paul.

Tallies a lot with some of the stuff we’ve been looking at in relation to legal personhood for non-human animals.

Some interesting examples from other jurisdictions, as you mention here.

Nice work.

Solicitor chipping in...

Doesn’t pursuing this line open a can of worms?

A couple of potential issues – (1) What are the characteristics of / constitutes a “non-human animal”? Does sentience come into play? Do we roll out personhood to all mammals? Insects? Bacteria (which are considered alive but not sentient)? (2) If a guardian of an animal with legal personhood fails to act in its best interests, who has locus to take action against that guardian?

I’m sure there’s more…

Seems unworkable to me.

Alan Robertshaw

Those are good questions; and ones that crop up a lot in this debate.

It’s a huge, and controversial topic, even within the animal rights community. But it’s an incremental approach (the ‘can of worms’). Great Apes seem to be the most obvious candidates to lead the way; and maybe cetaceans.

See here for example:

https://www.projetogap.org.br/en/noticia/cecilia-first-chimpanzee-released-by-habeas-corpus/

Commercial barrister

Great article

Rickster 67

As someone enjoying my environmental course I think this topic needs to be pursued until laws are passed to help protect all living organisms for future generations and the sustainability of the planet. This will not happen overnight but somehow we need the law makers to find a way so let’s start somewhere.

Join the conversation

Related Stories